What Is Science Studies for and Who
Cares?
George Levine
We are, self-evidently, at a moment of
aggressive public attack (some call it debate) on science studies. Just as the
wars against political correctness managed to deflect attention from the real
problems as an entrenched community appealed to democratic virtues while
defending privilege, so now well-funded and powerful forces are claiming to be
oppressed by the likes of Bruno Latour, Andrew Ross, and Katherine Hayles and
are attempting to trash--in the name of reason, truth, objectivity, justice,
and the first amendment--people who raise awkward questions.
Conferences of the National Association
of Scholars (NAS) (in November 1994) and of the New York Academy of Sciences
(NYAS) (May 1995) are symptomatic of an aggression that touches--perhaps
dangerously, perhaps only with a rather sad and silly paranoia--on some of the
most important issues of our time. While support for all serious intellectual
enterprises is being more than threatened by newly empowered anti-intellectual
political forces, these organizations are behaving as though the threat to
science is really corning from some of the few intellectuals who have taken the
trouble to think seriously about it. The excess and silliness of the response
may seem the mere pettishness of spoiled researchers used to big-time funding
and might well induce in us both complacency and a tendency to enjoy tweaking
for its own sake; but complacency or teasing are the last things we need at the
moment. Questions about the relations between society and science are among the
most important of our time. We need, rather, to be thinking about how our
healthy instincts to be oppositional might be channeled in more productive
directions.
The language of "holy war" should
remain the property of the egregious Norman Levitt and Paul Gross, who find an
antiscience leftist lurking behind every paragraph of science studies. For
them, irrationality and irresponsibility are pitted against the god of reason,
and
124 George Levine
they characterize scientists who join
our enterprise as apostates.1 There's not much profit for us in
adopting a rhetoric that pitches the interested nonscientific public against
science. Recent developments in the budget-cutting attempts to scale back
government support for work in both science and the arts and humanities ought
to be making it clear that our fates and our interests are entangled. We need
to be exploring the mutual interests of science and its critics and, to make
science studies genuinely effective, we need to persuade a lot of scientists
that what we are doing is not only in society's best interest but in theirs.
Popular skepticism about science derives not from the work of Latour, for
example, but from the distanced arrogance with which science operates its
magic, its ostensible contempt for lay questions and worries, its very power.
The best thing that could happen to science, if it wants to convince society
as a whole that it deserves support, would be to reject the arrogant language
of holy war and humanize itself. And in our efforts to assist in understanding
how science is involved in culture, how science is culture, it might profit us in the long run and for the
necessary battles to come to think more about our own strategies and, indeed,
about the degree of our own culpability in the obvious failures of relations
between practicing science and cultural critique.
Science studies, as we know, was born in controversy and sustains itself
controversially, largely against the scientific community that is the subject
of so much of its work. It has flourished, certainly, because the work of
science has in many ways been socially and politically determining in our
time--because, whether we like it or not, science, understood or not understood,
shapes our consciousness as it shapes the material conditions of our society.
We may be enthusiasts for science or frightened observers of its power, but we
know that we can't ignore it and that not to be aware of its power is not to be
educated.
Science studies has its own singular genealogies, growing from historical,
philosophical, sociological, as well as literary, concerns, but it is often
rather amusingly (if its implications weren't ultimately so serious) lumped
under the heading of postmodernism, where a lot of kooky, anti-intellectual,
politically correct, and subversive types have been thought to hang out. Even
the history and philosophy of science, which grew up as a field in the 1950s
and 1960s with a strong positivist bent and a deep commitment to science, is
now being accused of the sins of postmodernism. The strong positivism of the
early century was almost by definition skeptical about the degree to which
science's knowledge claims could be said to describe "reality."
And
Bas van Fraasen, whose contemporary mode of empiricism--which denies the
necessity of any claims about a reality out there for the validity of
scientific knowledge--would seem also to be "postmodern" in this wide
and unacceptable sense so often used as denunciation. But both the positivists
and van Fraasen have not worried scientists because, clearly, their projects
were not antiscience but attempts to establish the validity of scientific
knowledge. Since Thomas Kuhn's decisive Structure
of Scientific Revolutions early in the 1960s, however, scientists have been
particularly wary of historians of science and sociologists.
The squabbles that followed have now
been inflated to holy wars because there is so much at stake: intellectual
authority, educational direction, disciplinary turf, the allocation of big
money. Many more people than Levitt and Gross are taking cultural criticism of
science seriously because scientists are themselves feeling vulnerable. Their funding is getting cut, too. While
many of us linked to the humanities may feel especially ineffectual in the
world of politics, big money, and the public sphere, people are getting worried
that we are not ineffectual enough. The frightened announcement of the NAS
conference notes that our attacks are dangerous because, among other things,
they "alter directions of research" and "affect funding."
It is hard to believe that my consideration, for example, of the relation
between Darwin's views and Trollope's novels has contributed to the death of
the supercollider, but that is what the NAS conference is arguing implicitly.
Several years ago, when Steven Weinberg turned down an invitation to a
conference I was running, he told me that he knew what we were up to. I didn't
understand at the time, but clearly Weinberg's affiliation with the NAS
conference and his recent stern defenses of scientific rationality have most to
do with the supercollider, which should have been in Texas, where Weinberg
teaches. I want such serious thinkers on our side, but somehow he and others
have adopted the hysteria of Gross and Levitt and believe with the NAS and the
NYAS that there must be an important connection between the work of science
studies and Congress's decision that the supercollider was just too expensive.
As philosopher of science Paul A. Komesaroff put it, oh so delicately, about
eight years ago, "The two great bodies of thought, represented by natural
science and contemporary philosophy [in which he intended to include sociology
of science), have so far failed to make proper contact."2
How to do something about that contact?
A continuing and even naturalized consideration of science in the context of
culture is one of
126 George Levine
the urgent priorities of research and
education at our fin de siecle, but I don't have to convince you of that. From
our perspective, what's necessary is some clarification of what we are doing.
And so I want to ask some questions and gesture toward some answers.
Are we clear about whom we are
addressing, and for what reason? Are we clear about why even our most
professionally innocuous stabs at connecting science and literature are often
taken as assaults on science? It is certainly true that as an area of study,
"science and literature" has some large-scale objectives that extend
beyond the Arnoldian virtue of "Curiosity" and the disciplinary
injunction that we make our contributions to knowledge. Does our agenda entail
reform of the practices of the sciences? Are we involved in a sustained
critique of science that might have practical implications for how science is
funded by our society? What might it mean for us, in literature or other
nonscience disciplines, to suggest to scientists how they should do their work?
What do we think about scientists taking our discourse seriously enough to
suggest to us how we should do ours? Are we committed to showing how important
science is or has been to the way we write, think, feel, act? Or how pernicious
it has been?
Let's look at some of the fundamental
assumptions of our work. We always talk about science as though it is a
discourse. For example, in a brilliant recent book, Fact and Feeling, Jonathan Smith begins innocently enough
"with the assumption that science is a form of cultural discourse: like
literature or history or music or art or religion, it both shapes and is shaped
by the culture of which it is a part."3 Recognizing, as he
puts it, that the [nineteenth-century] "elevation of scientific discourse
. . . does not also isolate it from, or make it necessarily antithetical to,
other forms of discourse," Smith works hard, without denigrating either,
to break down the opposition between science and literature. It is difficult
for us to realize, because this is so much like mother's milk to us, that the
move is not only culturally counterintuitive, it is politically fraught. But
such a view is viper's poison to almost everybody else. That is, much that we
take for granted is very likely to cause us trouble outside our disciplinary or
interdisciplinary area--and all too little within it. Smith is healthily aware
that to talk of science as "merely" another discourse demeans
science, and demeans literature as well. To what degree, when we argue that
science is a discourse, and not an epistemologically decisive one, are we out
to diminish science and to elevate ourselves? That, by the way, is the
Gross-Levitt line.
What Is Science Studies For? 127
Since the current battles so easily
reduce to turf wars, we need to answer such questions as clearly as we can.
Certainly, many of us turned our attention to science studies because we were
fascinated by science and admired it enormously. But science itself is not, as
Smith reminds us, a "monolithic" entity; it is, rather, a complex and
continuing process that transforms and often supplies the materials for its
own critique as readily and as significantly as literary studies do. In-sofar
as we imagine science as an institution, formally embodied in the academy and
in a hierarchy of material practice all over the world, discussion of science
always has strong practical implications. We need to consider whether, as we
investigate relations between scientific and cultural discourse, we are in fact
implicitly attacking the institution. Looking around the university, literary
faculty find that science faculty teach less and earn more and have access to
funding beyond the humanist's fiscal imagination; science faculty find that
literary study is full of ambivalences and ambiguities and, alas, moralisms,
that would be totally discredited in their own fields. These practical,
cultural differences don't help. But they don't inevitably entail the
for-or-against rhetoric that is now dominating public discussion.
Gerald Holton, a speaker at the
November NAS conference, but one whose contributions to the cultural study of
science have been very valuable, devotes the long final chapter of his most
recent book, Science and Anti-Science, to the
"Anti-Science Phenomenon." Holton's argument is neither so
intemperate nor so homogenizing as Gross and Levitt's, but he is distinctly and
indeed reasonably concerned about a problem that bothers them, too--the terrible
ignorance of science that pervades our society. Holton makes a strong and
moving case for the social and political importance of sound scientific
knowledge in the tradition of Karl Popper's Open
Society and Its Enemies (1945), and traces a sometimes convincing
connection between the rejection of science and a dangerous right-wing descent
into authoritarianism. But that old and valuable liberal critique of
"closed" societies really has nothing to do with the present case. We
need to make that clear. Why is it that studies of science and culture must be
taken as opposed to "sound scientific knowledge"? Bruno Latour is
inevitably disparaged as wanting to abolish the distinction between science and
fiction.4 We might argue with Holton and show him not only that Latour is not
anti-science (indeed, he has presented himself recently as quite literally in
love with at least some aspects of science and technology and he works for the government
precisely on matters of technology), but that the abolition of the distinction
between science and fiction of which
128 George Levine
Latour talks need not be dangerous for
science--depending, of course, on what you mean by "science."
Holton's position should remind us that
resistance to critiques of science has a long and honorable history, as well as
a shady and grubby one. Our job is to show that the Popperian critique doesn't
work in relation to the central activities of science studies. Nobody is trying
to close down science, and the defensiveness that assumes that anyone who isn't
for it is somehow sacrilegiously against it needs to be overcome. Most science
studies work I know would never have been written if its authors were not fascinated
by science. Substantively, we continue our exploration of the complex
relations between science and literature, science and culture--the way they
support, reveal, test, and inform each other--most of the time without direct
attention to our contemporary disciplinary battles. But how does all this work
relate to the practice of scientists themselves--which is, after all, what they
are worrying about? One might well ask about our work, who cares? That is, who
cares beyond our own professional institutions?
The surprise for me at my home
institution was that the first person outside the humanities and social
sciences who cared, and the person who to this day cares most, is Norm Levitt. Higher Superstition may have been
largely provoked by a year the Center for the Critical Analysis of
Contemporary Culture at Rutgers devoted to issues of science and culture. We
invited people like Latour, Helen Longino, and Simon Schaffer; during this time
Levitt sneeringly borrowed my copy of Katherine Hayles's Chaos Bound. He cares with a passion, which might in fact be better
than the unselfconscious indifference with which the work of science studies is
treated by most of the scientific community.
What started in my career as (what I
imagined) a not very daring curiosity about the way science was affecting the
Victorian writers has suddenly become controversial. This may be because people
who otherwise wouldn't have cared at all about, say, the relations between
Darwin and Trollope, or thermodynamics and Pynchon (of which I solemnly and
academically wrote many years ago), are suddenly finding themselves vulnerable
sharers in a skimpily funded academic world. But it has been intellectually and
practically invigorating to know that my audience extends beyond my discipline
and that what I think and argue might actually get nonspecialists upset. I
thought I was working out of a deep, perhaps even mystified, respect for science;
I thought science was powerful, interesting, and difficult. Science
What Is Science Studies For? 129
studies in literature, insofar as it
thinly existed, rarely implied disrespect for science.
It's disingenuous not to recognize,
however, that many of us are in the humanities because we were bad at or turned
off by science; the ethos we joined tended, conventionally, toward
antiscience. That was certainly true in the pre-science studies days of the new
criticism. The romantic critique of science, peeping and botanizing on its
mother's grave and implicit, for example, in Carlyle's reaction of "mechanism,"
has continued to play itself out in both high and low culture. Its recent
manifestations in New Age mysticism and environmentalism is part of what
disturbs Holton, as it also disturbs me. When Levitt first attacked me and my
center, he used Whitman's "When I Heard the Learned Astronomer" as an
example of what's wrong with our attitudes toward science.
However sympathetic we may have become
to the astonishing activities and achievements of science, we bring with us the
ethos of our discipline, a set of attitudes and skepticisms that are in effect
institutionally opposed to the professional practices of science. It is
difficult not to think of science and literature as two distinct ways of
knowing and as almost antagonistic in their relationship to knowledge, to the
human, and to value. Our attempt to conflate all discourse as fiction becomes
an insult to the professional distinctness of the scientific disciplines. By
focusing on language and culture we seem to be declaring war.
I discovered, for example, that my
rather innocuous reading of Darwin in Darwin
and the Novelists had become at Rutgers a focal point for controversy about
constructivism well beyond the departments at Rutgers in which anyone might
have read the book. Our vice president, a polymathic member of another NAS,
the National Academy of Sciences, saw me as a flaming postmodernist (which to
this day takes my obsolescing breath away) and asked me to instruct the
university community about how I could reconcile postmodernism to Darwin's
scientific work. It was then, in fact, that Levitt and several of his
colleagues emerged snorting from the protesting majority. When at one point, I
assured a heckling scientist that he had nothing to worry about since I would
not be asked to referee scientific grant proposals, one woman in the audience
shouted out, "Thank God." So this was where my interest in George
Eliot had got me?.
The experience was disenchanting, if
amusing, because it made me aware as I had never been before that the two cultures
were really, perhaps incurably, separated. And it was not a Leavis/Snow
separation in
130 George Levine
which the virtue of "values"
was opposed to the virtue of "knowledge," but a disciplinary,
turf/economic separation, in which what was at stake was institutional
authority and government funding. The separation had little to do with the
epistemology that was the ostensible focus of attention; it was embedded deeply
in material conditions. I was forced to understand the degree to which the very
assumptions that ground the enterprise of humanist or social scientist
investigation of science imply what may be an irreducible professional
conflict. While I had come to praise Darwin, not to bury him, I was heard to be
burying him and the whole noble enterprise of objective science.
Although I am not convinced that the
current separation between science and science studies needs to be quite as
wide as it is becoming, I am convinced that we are in a turf battle. In
science studies we are claiming to say something important about science; we
are standing on somebody else's turf; our decision as nonscientists to study
science is a provocation to a discipline whose members have undergone strenuous
disciplinary training and who are now also having trouble finding jobs, as much
trouble as we are having. Their decision to fire back should not be surprising,
unless we are insufficiently aware of the degree to which we are in fact
trespassing and they feel themselves, from their positions of institutional
and financial power, very vulnerable indeed. As we resent, say, Gross and
Levitt's unintelligent critique of science studies, so scientists resent
Latour, Schaffer, and Shapin. We are not innocent.
There is a lot at stake in a cultural
criticism that might discourage public resources from supporting scientific
activity. Feminism is not merely the crazy and Stalinist political positioning
that Levitt and Gross caricature; theoretically, if people listen to it, it
could affect scientific projects, shift around the flow of money, cut it off
in other directions. David Berreby points out in Lingua Franca that
the outrage scientists feel for science
studies is fueled by more than intellectual disdain. Government and business
are funding less basic research in science. Congress has voted to kill the
superconducting supercollider. Doubts have been raised about the space station,
even about the human genome project. The turf is shrinking, and so, like tribes
forced toward the same oasis by a drought, scientists and sociologists of
science are starting to threaten and skirmish 5.
The announcement of the NAS conference
is revealing as it shouts that the attacks on science are
"dangerous." Here's why: "They undermine
What Is Science
Studies For? 131
public confidence;
they alter directions of research; they affect funding; they subvert the
standards of reason and proof." Here is very expensive and moralized turf.
Levitt and Gross take the high moral
line in talking about what troubles them, although they regard nonscientists'
questioning of the authority of scientific knowledge as medieval. What worries
them, they say, is that the larger culture, "which embraces the mass media
as well as the more serious processes of education," will lose its capability
"to interact fruitfully with the sciences, to draw insight from scientific
advances, and, above all, to evaluate science intelligently" (6). In a
book that mocks everything that doesn't understand science, it is almost funny
that the authors imply here that until these SLS-style critiques came along,
the public was interacting fruitfully with the sciences. They are, of course,
right that people aren't adequately educated in science, but blaming science
studies is both unhistorical and scapegoating. Science studies at least
encouraged an interest in science that before then required a Sputnik to
vivify. The autocratic and arrogant intellectual snobbery that becomes the
model for Gross and Levitt's contemptuous dismissal of meddlers in science is
far more likely to be responsible for the public's ignorance than the stars or
followers of science studies, who constitute a minute and uninfluential
minority when it comes to public power, congressional support funding, and
education. Gross and Levitt mean by fruitful interaction the public's total
deference to anything that the scientific communities might argue. The
interaction is to be all one way.
This is Gross and Levitt's real
concern: "In order to think critically about science, one must understand
it at a reasonably deep level. This task, if honestly approached, requires much
time and labor. In fact it is best started when one is young" (5). And why
do you suppose so many humanists are involved in these medieval exercises of
attack on the authority of scientific knowledge? Because, one might have
guessed, humanists are taking their revenge for having been the lowest disciplines
on the totem pole of epistemological authority: "Literary criticism, finally,
has been looked upon as a species of highly elaborated connoisseurship,
interesting and valuable, perhaps, but subjective beyond hope of redemption,
and thus out of the running in the epistemological sweepstakes" (12).
Unfortunately, the NAS/Gross-Levitt
position, seeming so extreme in its deliberately contemptuous formulations, is
pretty much the norm (except for questions of civility) in the communities of
science. The assumptions that mark most of our work and that I have quoted
132 George Levine
from Jonathan Smith's new book are
simply beyond the pale. We need to face the fact that these assumptions have
barely any life beyond societies like ours; and we should be spending a lot of
time and energy on how to move them beyond these conference walls.
Note, for example, what has been
happening in the response by science to the new national legislation known as
Goals 2000. As many of you are aware, the Department of Education is developing
guidelines on national standards for what children should know about the various
disciplines, and the NAS was given the responsibility to develop those
standards for the sciences. These are issues of enormous importance for the
future of education in America. The federal government is responding to the
public debate about what has gone wrong with contemporary education, and
federally imposed standards for all schools are only five or six years away. To
what degree do twenty-five years of science studies have anything to say about
these issues?
Let me quote a recent article from Science to give you an idea:
Some scientists were up in arms over
the description of the philosophy of science. Instead of saying that
researchers make discoveries, the document described science as a "social
activity" of "constructing knowledge," and emphasized the
"tentative nature of scientific knowledge." Physicist James Trefil of
George Mason University in Fairfax, Virginia, says the early version conveyed
"the really bizarre postmodern notion that somehow science is just a
matter of social convention, rather than analysis of data. Harvard University
physicist Eric Mazur, a pioneer in undergraduate teaching, was so dismayed by
this section that he resigned from the project immediately after reading it.
"Science is much more discovery-based than they seem to think," he
says.
But Trefil and other scientists give
[Richard] Klausner [the director of the project] high marks for his response.
Klausner insists the academy never intended to weaken the rigorous underpinnings
of the profession, and he says all hints of the offending philosophy will be
excised from the final draft.6
We may believe that scientists have
postmodernism all wrong, but we cannot ignore the horror most of them feel at
the idea of constructivism, which they see as threatening the rigorous
underpinnings of science. When I ask who cares about what we do in science
studies, I mean not only who is concerned with the dangers of our work, but who
can see its full implications and recognize its potential value. Who, for
example, understands that constructivism leaves the rigor-
What Is Science Studies Far? 133
ous underpinnings of science right
where they were and is part of a different project entirely? Who understands
that the implicit positivism of the educational program that seems to be
endorsed by the Academy is not only intellectually suspect but fundamentally
damages the relations of science to the culture as a whole?
Contemporary apologists for science are
on a crusade for reality. Objects fall through space at a certain rate not
subject to deconstructive analysis. It really happens, empirically. Gravity is
not constructed. It's out there. It's real. So what do we do with science and
reality? As an indication of our difficulties and responsibilities, I want to
look briefly at two key texts in our recent conceptions of the study of science
and literature and then raise one question about reality.
One of the most important figures for
us in the study of science and literature is Katherine Hayles, who does not
escape the direct wrath of Gross and Levitt. But when we turn to Chaos Bound, we find a book that is
pretty neutral politically (a ruse, Gross and Levitt suggest; the politics are
really there driving everything anyway). Hayles makes the mistake of beginning
her book by arguing that "different disciplines are drawn to similar
problems because the concerns underlying them are highly charged within a
prevailing cultural context."7 Such an argument implicitly
denies that science is intrinsically, not extrinsically, driven. There is no
connection between Godel's theorem and modernist art; there is no connection
between chaos theory and deconstruction. All science moves according to its own
internal logic, and the development of particular theories within it are not
related to cultural patterns.
I don't want to dwell here on Gross and
Levitt's absurd attack on Hayles. She has herself responded effectively, and
there is no longer any need to dwell on their well-known reductions and
simplifications. My point, simply, is that they serve as a good example of how
impossible it has been for those outside our discourse to accept or even
understand the assumptions with which we work. They see Hayles as denigrating
science because she talks about some scientific work as being akin to
postmodern literature. Her analyses, therefore, "in effect derogate the
reliability and accuracy of standard science, and snidely disparage those
scientists--that is to say, the vast majority of all scientists--who have been oblivious to this ostensible revolution
in thought" (92). This, I believe, would be a majority position among
those outside the humanities and some of the social sciences in the academy:
they have not bought into our talk about "langue" and
"parole," or into our sense of how culture works beyond the
intentions
134 George Levine
of the individuals who compose it. Here
is nonsense or Marxism, or worse.
For our part, however, we need, if we
believe in the sorts of culturewide analyses Hayles conducts, to make the
assumptions about culture that underlie them available to a world that sees
them as counterintuitive if not mad. This is probably harder than most of the
work we do. It's crucial that we make it clear that understanding the way
scientific and cultural attitudes interpenetrate need do no harm to science and
might well lead to that mythic lost ideal condition in which science and the
public interact creatively.
Second, let me turn briefly here to
Andrew Ross's work, which has developed some reputation among many of us. Strange Weather is not strictly a book
on science and literature. It belongs rather to the developing world of
cultural studies, takes as its dominant metaphor and subject the science of
weather prediction and the cable weather channel, and is written overtly in
the interest of what Ross calls progressive politics. Unlike Hayles, Ross has
a political agenda, and it's not hard to notice that he is not well loved by
those outside cultural studies in which he works. Ross makes it clear that he
doesn't know much about science, and yet he spends most of the book attempting
to undercut, for political reasons, the special authority of science against
protest movements like New Age activists.
What is most important about Ross's
book is that it is centrally concerned with the question of how a lay public
might most effectively relate to science, as institution and practice. This, I
take it, is the critical issue. He doesn't, after all, accept the ideas of the
protest movements he studies but is interested in the political significance
of their antiscientific positioning, and he criticizes these groups because
they argue their own authority by adopting some of the very strategies of the
sciences they critique. But the very audience we are trying to reach doesn't
seem to have the time or the training to understand what books like Ross's are
trying to do. What matters for them is that the book seems to be antiscience and
that it is driven by a political program.
Valuable and important as it is, Strange Weather may, rhetorically, be
striking the wrong note. It's the kind of problem we need to be thinking about
as we seek to extend our range beyond those initiates who begin with our
assumptions and our training. Ross is deliberately playful and theatrical
throughout the book--rather too much so, I think. The opening statement seems
impossible not to read as a provocation: "This book is dedicated to all
the science teachers I never had.
What Is Science Studies For? 135
It could only have been written without
them."8 That's cute, of course. And it places Ross rather aggressively, it
would seem, in the anti-science camp. The problem is, books written like this
depend on readers who like to play with language, but they are often, and I
believe most importantly, read by people who don't. Since one of the points of
Ross's book is that in order to act meaningfully in the politics of
contemporary culture, we need to become more
literate in science and technology, this opening aggression suggests a more
humble and science-favoring reading than it seems at first to allow. For Ross,
there is too much at stake to ignore science, and science is too important to
leave to scientists. I am not suggesting that Ross's provocations are
misguided. For anyone who can read, they open up the complications of the
subject. But for those who can't read, those whom we need to engage, those with
whom it would be good if we could "fruitfully interact," Ross's wit
is an alien language. It is no more intelligible to Gross and Levitt than the
technical language of Levitt's topological research is to me. Here, for
example, is the problem I'm most concerned with: the arrogance of specialist
discourse when we are talking to each other about things that matter.
I am particularly struck by the irony
that beyond the ignorances, aggressions, and brilliancies of disciplinary
difference, Ross in fact claims as his object something quite similar to what
Gross and Levitt claim to seek. Where they had asked for a lay public that
might "interact fruitfully with the sciences, . . . draw insight from
scientific advances, and, above all, . . . evaluate science
intelligently," Ross seeks workable strategies that address "the
desire for personal responsibility and control that will allow nonexperts to
make sense of the role of science in their everyday dealing with the social and
physical world" (29). Here he isn't being playful; this is what it's all
about. How can we create a reasonable and strategically effective critique of
science that might have some plausibility in the world beyond these walls?
What Ross resists and what needs
resisting are the political and economic implications of the scientific
culture of expertise. Scientists do know how some things work, so it seems
absurd not to accept their judgments, to open ourselves, as a lay public, to
scientific authority. But does that entail the pious submission to absolute
scientific authority on the part of the lay public whose very lives will be
determined by the choices scientists and their material supporters make? If
fruitful lay interaction depends on full scientific literacy, I fear that
abject, pious submission is all that lies before us---even, ironically, for most
scientists, who have no standing outside their own areas of expertise.
135 George Levine
Precisely that model provokes Ross to
his provocations and me to these reflections. Gross and Levitt show that
science claiming universal rationality and the right method and a community of
truth seekers gets loaded with a lot of political freight dangerous to anyone
who might question it. Of course, we would be fools to behave as though there
is no knowledge of the natural world to be had and that science has no
better shot at it than any other
professionals, or nonprofessionals.
How then to reconcile our respect for
science with our resistances to it, to recognize the need for knowledge and to
sustain our sense that science is in culture, that it is never any more
unpolluted by the society out of which it emerges than any other cultural
product, that the power of its knowledge production requires of us more, not
less, attention? Being playful while talking to a like-minded group alienates
those who need to be convinced. Pretending to ignorance may seem like
encouraging it, and the one thing people who engage in serious discussion of
difficult scientific/cultural issues cannot afford is ignorance.
Let me focus this problem with a simple
exemplary narrative, whose moral is banal and whose particular point is
probably well known to many of you. At Rutgers, we own a stretch of genuinely
virgin forest--Mettler's Woods, "the last remaining uncut upland forest
in central New Jersey."9The forest, as what was known as a
"climax" forest, is invaluable for research and teaching. The old
oaks in it are, on average, 235 years old. As a result, "no manipulation
or human disturbance" has been allowed there. The biologists who supervise
the forest believe that it was crucial to keep it at its present equilibrium,
and thus even spraying for gypsy moths has been disallowed. Supervision has
been careful and thoughtful. The aim has been preservation. Certainly, the
refusal to do anything to the forest but let it be without human interference
would, prima facie, meet the approval of most conservation groups, most people
concerned with ecological issues.
And yet, as several young Rutgers
scientists have noted, the forest is falling into decay. The old oaks are
failing to reproduce themselves and seem at last to be "senescing."
Somehow, the best of intentions and the best available ecological paradigms are
not working, and it has since been discovered that some ecologically unsound
camping and careless campfire building would have done wonders for the forest.
"It is becoming clear," the scientists now say, "that oak
species in many parts of the eastern United States require some sort of ground
fire for successful regeneration" (69).
What Is Science
Studies For? 137
Such a story is familiar--not much
different, except in scale, from the lesson of the fires in Yellowstone Park.
And the moral is that as we move out into large, substantive, cultural/scientific
issues such as ecology where most of us have strong feelings and commitments,
we simply have to know what we are talking about. Even preliminary social and
moral decisions like whether to preserve the woods or to preserve endangered
species require some "scientific" information. There are costs to
everything; how do we determine what the cost will be? If we decide that
preserving the woods is a good thing, we should first know why and second know
how to preserve them. That requires serious research, what is now called
scientific research. Ecologically, it turns out, it was a scientific mistake to treat humans as though they were not part of
nature; to save the woods, we need humans to burn them. And mistakes like that,
if we extrapolate to, say, the rain forests of South America, or even the
timberlands of the Northwest, have profound moral and political implications.
We are in a joint enterprise. Somebody is going to have to do the studying and
somebody is going to have to listen--on both sides.
In this context, the strategy of Ross's
book may seem at times unfortunate. I think that he is by and large
substantively right, and adopting the strategy of theater and provocation may
in fact be the way to get us talking about our mutual interests. But there is a
lot of educating on both sides to be done, and when we say in our various
literary, ecological, social, and cultural ventures that science is just
another discourse, we need to make it clear that we are not saying that as just
another discourse it doesn't have a particular and crucially important role to
play in anything we might choose to do.
Our interdisciplinary ambitions have
inadequately touched the people whose disciplines we want to talk about; our
rhetoric has been far too comfortable in affirming the dominant assumptions of
our curent work and on the whole too lax in affirming the necessity of the
kind of knowledge science produces best. And we have been insufficiently alert
to the way our assumptions and the very practices of our field embattle us and
alienate the scientific disciplines. Thinking always of science, that
nonmonolithic though institutionally powerful concept, as the enemy, reduces
our capacity to make our own discriminations, but more important, reduces our
capacity tot speak to those whose activities we most want to engage.
In any truly public battle, those
arguing for constructivism in general will lose to those arguing for reality
in general. What is necessary is first an at least rhetorical concession to the
power of the argument
138
George Levine
for reality, and second, a
demonstration of the way particular uses of the constructivist position are
humanly helpful and consistent with a rigorous science. It is crucial to make it
clear that even constructivists believe that it is necessary to know what they
are talking about, that the preservation of Mettler's Woods depends on sound
knowledge rigorously ascertained.
Some of the difference, the failure to
achieve appropriate contact, is irreducible, but some of it is not, and if we
are committed to a broader and richer conception of the interactions between
science and literature, of the place of science in the broader culture, we had
better make ourselves more alert and begin developing strategies that honor the
necessity for developing the constructivist and discourse-oriented critiques
we do so well, insisting on the most rigorous possible acquisition of
necessary knowledge, doing whatever we can to make it clear that nonscientists
have a place in the conversation, but finding above all a way to make
scientists part of that conversation.
Notes
This chapter was originally written for the keynote address of the Science
and Literature meeting In November 1994. In the course of revising it, I came
to realize that the audience I was addressing at that meeting is an important
part of the argument and that any revision that turned that audience into a
more generalized reader would lose much of its point. As a result, I have kept
the lecture's rhetoric and mean by "we" the members of the Science
and Literature Society, predominantly from departments of literature, but
including historians and scientists as well.
1 Norman
Levitt and Paul Cross, Higher
Superstition: The Academic Left and Its Quarrels with Science (Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1994), 6.
2
Paul A. Kotmesaroff, Objectivity, Science,
and Society (London: Routledge, 1986),
vii.
3 Jonathan
Smith, Fact and Feeling: Baconian Science
and the Nineteenth-Century Literary
imagination (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1994). 5.
4 Gerald
Holton, Science and Anti-Science (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993), 153.
5 David
Berreby, "That Damned Elusive Bruno Latour:' Lingua Franca 4, no.6 (1994): 24.
6 Science, 16
September 1994, 1649.
7 Katherine
Hayles, Chaos Bound (Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press, 1990), xi.
8 Andrew
Ross, Strange Weather: Culture, Science,
and Technology in the Age of Limits (London: Verso, 1991), i.
9 Steward
T. A. Pickett, V Thomas Parker, and Peggy L. Fiedler, "The New Paradigm
in Ecology: Implications for Conservation Biology above the Species
Level," in Conservation Biology: The
Theory and Practice of Nature Conservation and Management, ed. Peggy L.
Fiedler and Subodh K. Jain (London: chap-man and Hall, 1992), 68.